YouTube Transcript:
What is Real and What is not Real? with Prof Jan Westerhoff
Skip watching entire videos - get the full transcript, search for keywords, and copy with one click.
Share:
Video Transcript
Available languages:
View:
Right? So take a simple example that
that has doesn't have anything
specifically to do with the theories of
consciousness. Take colors, right? So we
um uh can make a fairly strong case for
the claim that colors aren't there in
the world independent of us because they
only get generated through the
interaction of stuff out there with our
particular visual system and the way our
eyes works and our our brain works and
so on. Right? So there isn't anything
out there in the world that is red. Uh
rather redness is a quality that arises
from the interaction of something out
there in the world say wavelengths of
lights or what have you and our specific
uh perceptual system. Right? So if you
took us and say all perceivers out of
the world then there would be no colors
Yan Westerov is professor of Buddhist
philosophy in the faculty of theology
and religion at the University of
Oxford. He has specific interests in
metaphysics and in the philosophy of
early Indian Buddhist thinkers. He's
written many books including the
non-existence of the real world, 12
examples of illusion and reality. a very
short introduction. So, welcome Jan Wes
to our discussion today. Um, I want to
talk about reality Yan and I want to um
begin if I may with Daycart because I
believe it was Poare
which made the comment that the man in
the street, the ordinary person is a
carteesian dualist. In other words, they
believe and most people believe they've
got a mind and they've got a body.
And my question to you is, what's wrong
with that? Let's call it the naive view.
Yeah. Um,
I don't think there's anything
specifically wrong with that as a first
pass. I would be surprised though if the
majority of people really consider
themselves to be cartisian jewelists
nowadays. I would think most people are
materialists and they think well they
have a body and the brain and somehow
the the the brain generates their mind
and um when when they die and the brain
disappears then they will disappear too
because if you are a cigian dualist then
you have to believe not only that that
is all wrong but that there are two
different kind of substances. There is
your physical body that is the the
physical substance and then there is
another substance which is a mental
substance which is you and in you as a
person these two substances are somehow
conjoined and then of course the
million-dollar question is how they can
interact and I mean that is that is one
of the one of the main problems that the
cases dualist has to solve and if you
you know want to want to start
criticizing that position that is
usually where it starts So you ask
yourself okay so can how's something
that is physical interact with something
that is non-physical because all the
interactions that we see in the physical
world is some physical stuff acting on
other physical stuff.
So that that is really what uh what you
think is unsatisfactory about the the
cartisian position. But uh I think as as
a position on reality I I would be
surprised if we find that many people
who still believe that
inside them is an indestructible
non-physical substance that is their
mind. I would I would think that all the
religious people would think that
certainly and there's what I I saw a
statistic the other day 1.4 billion
Christians and another 1.3 billion
Muslims and many others they would all
probably be I would guess um dualists
because of their religion. Um but
certainly I would say that most philosophers,
philosophers,
most thinkers and most university people
would all be materialists, nearly all of
them. And I wondered um and that
suggests then that everything is made up
of matter. It's made up of particles and
fields, maybe gluons, partons, whatever
they may be. And uh and therefore the
mind is somehow a mere phenomenon that
comes out of this interaction of matter.
Is that a good picture? Does that work? Yeah.
Yeah.
Well, that is a that's a complex
question and um it's on on the one hand
the answer is it it gets us very far
because we can explain a lot about how
the mind works by insight into how the
brain works right so various mental
functions we can explain how they're
generated by the brain and so on. Um now
the question is whether that explanation
gets us all the way and uh allows us to
explain the entirety of consciousness
and that is an entirely different
question and there things get a lot more
murky. So um one uh problem that is I
think interesting to consider in this
context is that you if you cons conceive
of the world and yourself as something
that your brain generates. So that when
you you are basically living in a kind
of simulated reality that is generated
by your brain and of course from input
through the through the physical senses.
Um then you immediately faced with the
problem that the entire setup that
generates that
virtual reality namely the brain and
everything else is also part of the
model or of the virtual reality itself.
Right? So you suddenly through this kind
of neurobiological reduction you are you
seem to be trapped in a loop right where
you say you are that um the world
surrounding you is a is a um is a
simulation of your brain and your brain
is comp is a part of the world and
therefore that is part of the simulation
too. So then of course the question is
to which extent that still is a stable
position and uh um there can be
different views on that. Some people
think it is um but in any case it is far
far from straightforward
straightforward
what position you should then take
regarding the reality of the brain as a
So if you do take that as the view
though, that surely implies that the mind
mind
is really just an illusion. It's a very
clever illusion and we think that we've
got a mind but the reality is that we
haven't. Is that um
um
yeah to of course that that then depends
on what you mean by illusion. So if by
illusion you mean something that reduces
to something else
then you'd say okay well in that case
the mind is an illusion. If you say an
illusion is something that isn't really
there, that doesn't really exist, then
that doesn't necessarily follow because
the in in that uh setup you still have
the appearance of a mind and that is
presumably doing something and that is
there. So the the the the existence and
the presence of the appearance
uh seems to be pretty um
pretty undoubtable. I mean there there
are people who who who
um worry about that as well and you get
this kind of illusionism about
consciousness where the idea is that
that is that that is simply illusory as
well. But if you for a moment stick to
the to the fact that consciousness at
least appears to you then of course the
the next question that arises is okay so
that might well be reducible to
something else. So that is is reducible
to um
phenomena but that doesn't mean that
it's not there doesn't have anything
specifically to do with the theories of
consciousness take colors right so we um
uh can make a fairly strong case for the
claim that colors aren't there in the
world independent of us because they
only get generated through the
interaction of stuff out there with our
particular visual system and the way our
eyes works and our our brain works and
so on. Right? So there isn't anything
out there in the world that is red. Uh
rather redness is a quality that arises
from the interaction of something out
there in the world say wavelengths of
lights or what have you and our specific
uh perceptual system. Right? So if you
took us and say all perceivers out of
the world then there would be no colors
and there would be no redness right.
Yeah. But that doesn't mean that once
you have a human being say uh nothing is
colored because you still have the
appearance of color and it just reduces
to something else. It is in fact not
some kind of primitive quality but it's
something that only arises as a complic
complex interaction from some stuff that
is outside and from some stuff that is
inside. So to that that extent on the
one hand yes red is illusory in so far
as it reduces to something else but it's
not illusory in so far it is still
appears right let me let me try to
clarify my question a bit when I talk
about something being illusurary and
whether the mind is illusurary I'm
referring really to to the idea of
epifenomenalism which my understanding
and I'm not a philosopher but my
understanding of it is that that matter
produces is the idea of a mind
rather as a kind of a byproduct.
And the way that you can see this quite
clearly is that um if it's merely
epifenomenal, if it's a if it's a
phenomenon of matter, then the mind
doesn't actually cause anything to
happen. Rather, it's the matter which
causes the mind to happen. So if I say
I'm going to make my hands raise in the
air like I just did, I think to myself
was doing that. But the reality is that
the mind doesn't cause anything. It was
determined by some laws of physics maybe
back before the beginning of the world
as it just playing itself out and it was
determined by some laws or other that
that's exactly what would happen at this
particular time. the mind didn't cause
it, but rather the materialism was the
cause of things.
Does that Yeah, that's that's right. So
the so the idea with with phenomenalism
is that you have some sort of underlying
base reality, say material reality here,
and then you've got some other
phenomenon sort of sits on top. So
that's the epiphenomenon, right? And the
important point about that scenario is
that causal relations only go one way,
right? So it's only going up from the
basis to the epiphenomenon. that's
causing the stuff but there's nothing
going down. Yeah. So that's what I meant
by illusion. We we think that it's going
down but it doesn't in reality right.
Yeah. So um uh yeah I'm I'm not sure
whether that is a good uh uh conception
in general to think of things being
illusory because we have many examples
where illusions have causal power.
Right? So just take two two at at
random. Say um assuming you dream of
some kind of imaginary scenario. You're
in a jungle um and being being chased by
a tiger. You lie in your bed sleeping.
What's your dream that? But because of
that dream, your heart heart rate goes
up, right? Because of the stress and the
adrenaline rush being chased by a tiger,
right? Okay. So here you think, well,
what is happening? Well, your mind is is
or your brain is generating the dream,
but then the dream has consequences on
the state of your physical body as
you're lying in bed, right? So, it seems
to be the case that that even though
it's illusory, it has causal powers. Yeah.
Yeah.
Uh take take another example. You see a
mirage in the desert that that is
presumably an illusion. There is no
water there. But the uh the um uh
illusion itself might have all kinds of
causal powers that generates specific
actions. For example, you might walk
into that direction because you see the
water over there rather than in the
other direction. Right. So it's causing
something to happen even though it is
only illusory. Yeah. So the the the
claim that if something is an illusion
then it doesn't do anything or it isn't
involved in causal processes or can't
cause uh any phenomena is perhaps not
the best way of getting to a general
idea of what it means for something to
be not real or something to be illusory.
Okay. So what would you say say the mind
is? I mean how how should we understand
it? As you say, most people take a most
philosophers seem to take a
materialistic point of view. Therefore,
what is the status of the mind
and consciousness correspondingly?
Right. Well, you have um of course two
obvious opposed positions on the table
here. Perhaps three with cartisian
dualism being in the middle. On the one
hand you have the you have the
materialist position where where matter
or the brain generates the mind. Then on
the other hand you've got the idealist
extreme where you say okay it's all
really mental and this then generates
the appearance of matter. Yeah. And then
of course you have you've got sort of
dualist halfway house positions where
you say well there's both material stuff
and there's mental stuff and then you
somehow have to um generate uh some kind
of interaction between the two in order
to see how it works. Right? So I'm
personally I'm I'm I'm not a fan of
either of these three positions. Now in
particular as um they
both of those all three of those assume
some kind of some kind of
foundationalism. They they assume that
you have some sort of base reality that
is really there that is that is is
fundamental and on which everything
rests and then you've got all the other
stuff that is generated from that. Yeah.
So um I'm more interested in and and
also more convinced by accounts
according to which you have all these
kinds of different things and they
condition one another. Right? So you've
got mental things and you've got
physical things and none of them is
reducible to another thing but they
depend on the on each other in complex
ways. So it is the brain that generates
the mental stuff. But then of course
without the mental stuff we don't have
certainly don't have any epistemic way
to any material. Right? So without um um
without us having a mind there is no way
that the world as it appears to us would
appear to us. Right? So these two seem
to be connected in sort of complex
interactions and and mutual dependence.
And in which case it wouldn't be the
case that you can simply reduce one to
some kind of foundation and then
everything else is sits on top of that
reduction base. So would you say that
there is no
ultimate foundation? We know I was
trained as a physicist and we started
off saying that there were such things
as molecules and then we reduced the
molecules down to atoms and elements and
then we reduced those down to nuclei and
protons and then below those we found
that there might be quarks and there
might be gluons and there may be things
below those as well. But this is rather
like that philosophical answer saying
that everything sits on the back of the
elephant and then the elephant sits on
the back of the turtle and what's below
the turtle and it goes on and on. Maybe
it's turtles all the way down, but you
know, um, or are you saying there isn't
a picture like that? That picture is a
fake or false picture, and we shouldn't
be beguiled by it.
Yeah. You see, there are um
there are basically two alternatives to
the kind of foundationalist picture that
you've that you've just presented. So um
on the foundational system you've got
some sort of rock bottom other material
rock bottom or some kind of mental rock
bottom of stuffs that that is just brute
is just there. There's no further
explanation for it and then everything
sits on top of that. Yeah. So um you've
got some kind of dependence base and
dependence relations all reduced to
that. Um now there are two different
alternatives to that picture. one is the
the one you've just mentioned where it's
dependence all the way down. Right? So
for every base layer you can find a more
fundamental base layer that one depends
on and that one depends on and that one
that one depends on. Right? And um that
is um u if you want to say have a have a
simple model of that you consider the
the um negative natural numbers -1 - 2
-3 and so on. they go all the way back
and for every negative number you can
find another one that is smaller and you
never reach the end of that sequence.
Yeah, but that isn't a problem. I mean,
you don't have to think, well, for all
these negative numbers to be there and
for one of them to be smaller than
another one, there has to be a smallest
negative number that sits at the bottom
of the of at the end of the chain,
right? There isn't. It goes all the way
back. Yeah. So, there in the same way,
you could think, okay, well, it's
dependence all the way around all the
way back. uh and there isn't a a
fundamental dependence level. Okay, so
that is that that is is one possibility.
The other possibility is to say well it
is basically a huge circle, right? So it
goes the dependence relations go all the
way around and so A depends on B and B
depends on C and so on and then you get
a really big arc and in the end it
closes back on itself. Right? Now um if
the if that circle is really big then it
might look to uh your limited
perspective like a line because you
don't actually see the other end and
where it closes back on itself. Um but
it might nevertheless be a kind of
circular dependent structure. Right? So
those are the kind two two main
alternative models that you can um uh
that you can oppose to this kind of
foundationalist system and I think
they're both quite quite interesting um
both intrinsically and also because they
haven't gotten that much air time in
metaphysics and ontology until
relatively recently because people were
often worried and said okay well isn't
there in the case of the of of the
infinite descent isn't that an infinite
regress which is going to lead us to a
contradiction somewhere and the similar
way with a circularity right you think
you'll you'll end up with something uh
that that ends up somewhere in saying
you know a and not a and then you've got
a problem but um I think people are now
fairly clear that this is not the case
and that these structures are all
consistent in the same way in which the
uh foundationalist system is consistent
meaning that you can't derive a
contradiction from them and then the
interesting question is you know which
ones work best in order to explain what
we want to explain, right? And uh then
you can say well if for example you you
consider the example of the body and the
mind then you have these various
foundationalist systems and all of them
come with specific problems and specific
uh difficulties and then you think okay
well perhaps we can we can solve the
issue better by considering
uh other possible structural approaches
in which this could work. So either this
kind of infinite descent of of of
dependence relations or a kind of
circular structure where it's not that
uh um everything depends on some
fundamental basis but where you have a
mutual interdependence of things in a
complex structure and in and in in a
kind of web where where you also get
I mean This has implications for the
whole program really of
theoretical physics of physics itself
because over the past 50 years or so
there's been a great push to obtain what
might be called the grand unified theory
which means to be able to explain
everything in terms of some fundamental elements
elements
particularly to unite gravity and
Einstein's general theory with quantum
mechanics because they don't seem to fit
terribly well together, but they're
looking for a grand theory which will
sit below there and then will it explain
everything. Now, would you say that such
a quest the actual program itself is
doomed to failure even before they the
search begins?
Well, I I I don't think as a as a
philosopher I really should put about
projects in physics. I mean I could but
I don't think this is this is a very
very sensible route to take. Um look I
mean there are
there are lots of different theoretical
approaches that are explored in physics
in particular when it comes to thinking
about the the very foundations of
reality. Some of which are
foundationalist some of which are
relationist and and so on. And um what
what works in the end only time will
tell. Um
I think what is what is important at at
this stage is to be to be aware of the
variety of different structures that
reality might have. So to make sure that
we at least have a more or less
comprehensive coverage of the way things
could be and that's certainly the the
kind of foundationalist approach which
is in many ways the the the
most natural one where you think okay
well nature is made just like like a
Lego structure out of Legos and all we
have to do is break it down down down
until we reach the smallest bricks and
then we can rebuild up everything from
there. that that is not the only way we
could explain things. Yeah. And then
whether the alternative approaches works
work better and so on is this is of
course a question which is then uh
subject to empirical confirmation not
not not simply armchair theorizing.
So how okay how do we how do we
determine let me put the question this
way. How do we determine or is there a
criterion of demarcation
between what is real and what is not
real? You know, one tends to think
building blocks, whatever they are, they
would be elements of reality as such.
But then the question that you're posing
really is what
is there a difference between the real
and the the unreal? Can we decide you
know what what category something falls
into? This is a category of being in the
real camp and this is a category of of a
notreal thing. Does such a criterion exist?
exist?
Yeah, there there are various in fact
there are various criteria here that you
can appeal to and some of which are of
course more
suitable or useful than others. So um if
you if you start at the at the most
basic level you you could say well um
what is real is
whatever appears to you and that's not
very satisfactory because all kinds of
illusory stuff can appear to you and you
might might uh make that a bit more
rigorous by saying okay so what is real
is what appears to more than one person
right so if I have an hallucination I
can ask my neighbor whether he sees the
same thing that I think when I when I
see a pink elephant floating in the sky
and if they see it too then perhaps I'm
more convinced that there really is a
pink elephant floating in course you're
assuming there is a neighbor as part of
that reality I mean we're really back to
daycart here aren't we you know the the
kito go some I I think therefore that's
the only reality that I can be assured
of the only thing which I can be
confident that really does exist is my
myself because I
Yeah, I I'm I'm not entirely sure
whether uh well whether that is even
getting us all we want to get. I mean
even even quite early on Lenbach made
the point that he thinks well all he can
really get at this stage is that there's
thinking going on right whether there's
a subject that does the thinking is of
course already an inference at least you
can have the you can have some kind of
process but whether the process comes
with a subject um is not so clear um
yeah so I mean I mean getting getting
back to to different ways of defining
this kind of division between the
illusory and and reality. So um inter
subjective agreement is not a very good
demarcation either simply because you
know you can have collective delusions
or collective hallucinations where
people would see the same illusory
thing. So um I think we're getting
somewhat into more interesting territory
when we are thinking of Dr. Johnson's
story and the stone when he you know
tried to tried to refute Barklayan
idealism by kicking a stone and saying I
refute it thus what is meant there is of
course that what is real puts some kind
of um push back to our desires and our
wishes right so we might want to uh be
able to put our hand through the wall
but when we do that we realize there's
obstruction there and that shows her
that the wall is real and not illusory
yeah um that's one of many definitions
of reality that you you provide in your
book reality, don't you? Yes, that is
one this is one way of thinking about
it. It's I I don't think it's it's it's
certainly better than the last two I've
just discussed, but it's uh also not
quite there simply because you uh uh can
be in situations where reality pushes
back and you're still in an illusory
situation. So you might be in a dream or
you might be playing a video game and
manipulating characters and you want to
do something and that doesn't work
because it uh the game is not programmed
that way and so on. So just the fact
that that you've got some sort of push
back doesn't mean that you are not in
some kind of illusory scenario. So I
think the two two main uh criteria that
really work much better are um uh uh one
of which we've we've already talked
about is in terms of dependence chains.
So when we say okay so if if something
depends on another thing for example
like an like an effect depends on its
cause or like an structure that is made
of parts depends on its parts then what
is real is what you get when you go down
the dependence chain. Right? So if you
if you trace back the chain of causes
you get to you the further you go back
the more and more real it get or if you
if you trace a thing back to its parts
then the parts are more real than the
whole. So in putting it a bit more
abstract you would want to say well what
is real is where all these dependence
chains stop right whether these are part
whole dependencies or causal
dependencies and so on you trace them
back to their source and that's that's
what is real and everything else is
really just a construction from that. So
that that is one way of um
of conceiving of of of what is real and
what is me merely appearance. Another
way that I think we've also alluded to
at least um is the uh is mind
independence. Right? So if you imagine
you took all of the observers or humans
or animals want everything that has a
mind out of the universe and then you
ask yourself okay so what would be left
and all of that is left that is real and
everything else is just a mind-made
construct right so to that extent you
would want to say well if you take all
these these perceivers out then
certainly all colors would be gone and
all smells and all tastes and perhaps
moral properties and so on and so on but
that uh presumably still you know electrons
electrons
uh and
atoms and so on. So to that extent you
have really two
criteria I think that that are really
fundamental in this discussion about
what is real and what what is not. One
is mind independence and the second one
is where the dependence chain stops.
There's a there's a third element there
because I think Barkley would have said
that even if you take all the humans out
that there is no mind to perceive
there's still the mind of God which
maintains everything in the background. Yeah.
Yeah.
But I'm not sure if that's a red herring
on this this particular Well, I mean,
you see that that is that that was
essential for Barklayan idealism because
if you reduce everything to ideas in
minds, then uh you might not want to
reduce it just to ideas in my mind and
in your mind, but you need something
more fundamental or less subjective and
even less interubjective than that and
that is the mind of God for in in in the
Bian system right other than other than
of course the idea that if you if you
take that to its logical extreme then
you end up with what's called solivism
don't you that's the idea that only
minds exist but really only my mind
exists and there is nothing else in the
entire universe other than me. Mhm.
You've written about about that. What's
your what's your view of solitism as a
as a coherent philosophical view?
Yeah, that is that's quite interesting.
I mean, this is of course the the the um
uh logical extreme of an idealist
position, right? So you first of all you
start with a world with stuff in it and
then you reduce it all to mind and then
you ask yourself okay well but other
people of course like you know you and
and and and so on they are external
objects as well and if I got rid of the
table and the chair and say that's just
mental then you are just mental too but
you're just mental in my mind right and
so then everything gets shrunk together
into um uh into one mind and um then you
have then you say might say to yourself,
okay, so the only thing that's really
real is me and my ideas and and stuff
that's happening in my mind and then
you've got the solidist conception.
Yeah. Now um uh of course this is
usually not regarded as a very plausible
or attractive philosophical position. So
apparently there are no philosophers who
take this view apparently. Um so well I
mean there should only be one of course
there should only be one but we don't
know who it is a figment of their
imagination I suppose. Apparently, one
person according to John Zo wrote to um
wrote to uh um Bertrram Russell and said
that I am a soypist I've discovered and
I'm so happy about and I don't know why
more people aren't that way inclined but
um join the soypist society.
Uh yeah. So I mean take take into
account though that um um when we think
about our arguments for why there are
actually other minds than our own minds
um we usually use an argument from
analogy. Right? So how do I know that
you have a mind? Well I see that you
have a body and that you carry out
certain behavior and say you speak and
you raise your hand and and things like
that. And then I think okay so probably
you are more or less like me and so when
I raise my hand there is be just before
that there's some stuff going on in my
mind my intention to raise my hand so I
think when you are raising your hand
it's probably the case that there's
something happening in your mind as well
because I don't make you raise your
hands I just see your hand going up so I
assume by analogy you being more or less
like me that there's also some something
going on in your mind. Yeah. So that's
that's usually the the the argument how
we can infer that other people around us
are not zombies but that they actually
have minds. Yeah. Now this inferential
rule is of course open to the soypist
right. I mean he or she can also think
that well by analogy I assume that there
are other people with other minds
precisely on the basis of the same data
that we get as well. Right? So um even
if we think on in in for various reasons
that that solypism is an unsatisfactory
position it's still the case that we
don't have direct access to anybody's
mind either right I can't look into your
mind and see that you have one I can
only infer it and the way I infer it
would be exactly the same mechanism that
a soypist would use in order to infer
that they are the minds yeah So um the
so the the the existence of other minds
is really something which uh is it comes
at the end of a chain of inference. It's
not a piece of data that we could just
take. So solypism cannot be refuted is
what you're saying. Whatever evidence is
presented nothing can actually refute
it. You simply have to either believe it
or not I suppose. Um yeah, I mean it's
the the question is of course whether
that's usually the way you pick or
decide between different philosophical
positions, right? So, and there's there
was a there's an interesting passage in
in in in Robert Nosik where where he's
wondering about that and says okay so um
so what what does it actually take to
refute a philosophical argument and um
of course you know few philosophers are
convinced by arguments that try to
refute what they believe and you think
okay well the best thing would be a kind
of you know philosophical argument that
if somebody who
if you present the proof to them and
they they don't see they don't agree
agree to is then their mind explodes.
Right? So this is you know the ultimate
reputation. So if you don't if if you
don't agree to the argument then you die
now that that is of course not how it
works in philosophy and I certainly
haven't come across an argument that
would be that powerful. Usually what you
say is you have various philosophical
views um that can explain certain
certain phenomena and all of them come
with explanatory benefits things they
can explain and they come with with
costs. So there's certain assumptions
you have to make in order to get the
theory to go right and what you do is
usually you try to do some kind of
weighing between the things you need to
accept. So the the philosophical costs
of the view and the what it delivers the
the benefits what it can explain. Yeah.
And then you you will find uh a lot of
people saying well I mean with with kind
of soypism it's just not such an
attractive position. Right. You uh uh
I'm just not willing to make the kinds
of assumptions that you need to make in
order to take these positions. And I
think I wouldn't really
um assume that it's a particularly um e
either interesting or explanatory
position to take on reality to thinkers
will just spinning out of my mind. Yeah.
So that's one way in which you can say
you you refute the position but not
because you find some kind of you know
logical flaw in it and say it reduces to
a contradiction or because you say well
if you don't believe in that then your
mind is going to explode but simply by
saying look um there there are costs
benefits in in theoretical terms to this
view and I think in in the balance it
doesn't come out as strong as others and
I'd rather uh believe in the existence
of other minds than not. I I've always
felt that the difference between philosophy
philosophy
and science, if we take if we take
Popper's definition of science for the
moment, that it's that which is
falsifiable, potentially falsifiable
statements. Philosophy doesn't contain
any potentially falsifiable statements.
It's not refutable in that sense. You
can only test it through its logical
consistency, not through reputation or
falsifiability in the scientific sense.
And that could be a in my view a de a
demarcation between philosophy and
science. Would you go along with that?
No, I don't think so. I mean the the um
the difficulty is that um the uh the way
um evidence and beliefs are linked up
with one another is I think a lot more a
lot more complex. So the the the Quin
has has the metaphor there of the web of
belief, right? So the the idea is that
our our beliefs and what we what we take
to be true about the world and our um
beliefs about what we perceive and so
on. So they are they are interconnected
in a complex web of confirmation and and
disisconfirmation. Yeah. And um usually
if you say okay so if you get some uh
evidence coming in that contradicts your
predictions. You you think you the
experiment should say that but in fact
it says something else. Then you're
going to adjust your beliefs. Right?
This is kind of a falsification route.
You make the assumption first and then
you falsify it. you assume the opposite
of it and then you continue. Uh why do
you do that? Well, in order to make the
system consistent again, right? So you
you it predicted a and then you get the
get the data not a. Um if you take that
on as a belief, then you believe in a
and not a that's obviously problematic
because you want to be consistent. So
because you can't change um uh you can't
change the input, you're changing the
beliefs that you have. So that is
basically the falsificationist position.
However, what makes it more complicated
is in order to ensure consistency in the
system, there are all kinds of changes
you can make, right? One change you can
make is of course you say, okay, well,
it looks as if the the experimental
results says that, but I actually don't
think that that device you're using here
is quite reliable. That's a bug
actually. It shouldn't be saying that,
right? So, we we restore consistency by
saying, well, that thing is actually a
bit dodgy. We need another apparatus. We
try that again, right?
or there are other places within the web
of belief that you can tweak in order to
restore consistency. Some of these will
be extremely eccentric and unattractive.
And the the ex the the extreme that you
can see in this in this conception is
say if you look at con conspiracy
theories, right? Whatever evidence you
produce, there is a way of immunizing
the the theory against that stuff,
right? So um so to that extent you can
you can restore consistency no matter
what comes in as an information. That is
of course not a um not a general
cognitive strategy either. I mean what
you want is kind of a good good balance
between uh taking account of the
evidence but also being aware of the
fact that the evidence might be
deceptive and that there might be a bug
in the apparatus or you might have set
up the experiment in a in in a dodgy way
and that you therefore want to hold on
to your theory a little bit longer and
don't just ditch it at the first
recalculant piece of data. Right? So to
that extent it's um uh the I mean the
the whole question of of of whether you
regard some data as fortificatory or not
is not simply coming
from the data saying okay so we've got
you because you've got that data you you
have to change your beliefs but you
rather want to say okay so how do I
balance the entire web of my beliefs in
in a way that it's both consistent but
also presents the best explanation of
the data that are coming in. Yeah, we're
moving here away from Papa towards
Thomas aren't we? Because he talks
about this whole structure, this this
web which which a bit like a paradigm
which which predisposes your your views
of the world in a particular way and it
takes a huge shift sometimes a
generational shift to move away from one
one picture one set of beliefs to
another set of beliefs. It can be quite
revolutionary. Yeah, that's right.
Right. So this is K is Thomas K is one
example and Paul fire is another
philosopher of science who uh were not
convinced by this falsificationist
picture. I think in in general um uh if
you take this kind of web of belief uh
account on board then you get much
closer in sort of structured uh to what
when you compare philosophical theories
and and um um scientific theories
because in kind of philosophical
theories you there are also particular
problems and puzzles you want to solve
right so you want to you know you've got
something like the ship of thesis you
know is the is still the same same ship
if you replace all the planks or you've
got the question you know are moral
values out there or is it just what I
find disagreeable or or agreeable and so
on so you've got these kind of puzzles
or problems and then you tend to try to
come up with a theory that explains them
and gives you an answer in one way or
another and does that in a sort of
systematic way and usually there are
various theories that that that can do
that and they often contradict each
other and then how do you pick well The
best way of picking is by saying okay so
for this theory to work you have to
assume a b and c and for that other
theory you to work you have to assume d
and e and f and which one do you think
is the more attractive package to uh to
accept in terms of the theoretical costs
that you run by making these assumptions
and the explanatory power you gain by
solving the puzzles. Right? And then
it's the the the question is just not
what refutes what but what overall
presents the best deal. And of course
that doesn't mean that there are not a
lot of approaches that are ruled out in
this way because often you can say well
that approach is definitely not as good
as that one so we're not going to take
that but then we have two others here
and that might then be a draw. Yeah.
Yeah. So that in that in that way the
the the the discussion is a lot more
holistic than just saying okay which
argument is refuted by which other
argument. Okay. Now I know that you've
studied Buddhist teachings quite
extensively. I just wonder how has that study
study
informed your view of reality or or
affected your view of reality?
Right. Well, of course, in in in
Buddhist philosophy and also in Buddhist
philosophy in India, which is is ma
mainly what what I've I've worked on in
the past, you get all sorts of different
views of reality, right? So, they don't
even though they are all Buddhists, they
don't all have the same philosophical
position. Yeah. So you have um uh people
who believe that there basically a kind
of fundament kind of foundationalism is
true that there basic objects out of
which everything is made. Then you've
got others who believe that everything
is mental only and everything is only a
mental construction. And then you've got
a third group of of of philosophers who
think that um mind isn't fundamentally
real either. But in fact, you've got
this kind of complex uh web of things
one one thing dependent on another. And
so there is actually nothing that is uh
um um substantial or independent, but
you've got sort of one one complex web
of things depending on each other. So um
I mean in my in my uh study of these
systems I I was you know first of all
interested in
connecting them up with much of the
discussion that we find in in
contemporary metaphysics and
epistemology and so on because it it
struck struck me certainly as when when
I studied started studying these
materials that they were often treated
very much in in isolation or were were
studied primarily arily from a uh from a
philological uh point of view or from
from a religious studies point of view
um but not so much taking them uh taking
them seriously philosophically and
asking yourself okay so what are the
arguments that these people present and
are the arguments actually good ones and
does the does the conclusion follow from
the premises and so on. So this is what
what what what um interested me in in in
working in these materials in in the
first place, seeing so so how how uh
there is actually potential for
developing that um systematically and um
I then got particularly interested in um
certain ideas of basically non
non-foundationalist ontology. which
which are developed quite extensively in
Indian um philosophical Indian Buddhist
philosophical materials and and and
their later Asian successes.
And um whilst that is whilst these
constitute ideas that you do find to
some extent in the western philosophical
tradition, it was never very prominent
there. Yeah. And then I thought okay so
this is quite interesting in in in terms
of developing philosophical positions of
course we we we want to you know explore
all the kind of theoretical
possibilities and see okay so if if if
something doesn't work what else could
be working and as such it struck me that
this presents a really interesting
alternative way of thinking about um
phenomena and something that could well
be developed in a purely systematic
manner and so this is what partly what
I've been trying to to do in this uh
book the non-existence of the real world
which is really taking some ideas from
uh the the Indian philosophical uh
tradition so in particular a school a
school called Madyamaka and trying to
develop that in a purely systematic
manner so saying so so saying not the
the justification is that it says
something in the text but you say okay
we'll start with specific fundamental
ideas and then see how we can develop
systematic developments of these kinds
of conclusions and can you summarize the
the teaching of that miamaka is it um
yeah so the the I think the fundamental
idea of of madamaka is um a kind of anti-foundationalism
anti-foundationalism
right so they argue against the position
that there are any entities that exist
with intrinsic nature so things that
have their existence their being their essence
essence
just by themselves without depending on
other things. Right? So this is
relatively close to what in the western
conception you uh associate with certain
ideas of substance. Right? So substance
start to to stand beyond. So it's that
kind of stuff which sits at the bottom
and then everything all the accidents
all the properties and so on and then
build on top of that. Yeah. So if you
say there are no substances then of
course you get back to the very problem
that we had earlier on. So whether it's
either turtles all the way down or it's
some kind of some kind of big loop and
um so the so the developing the further
consequences of this idea that you don't
have a foundation
within reality and you don't have a
foundation in in epistemology either. So
you don't have uh fundamental or basic
beliefs that are not grounded in
anything else either. Trying to develop
the consequences of that is basically a
a large part of the systematic
development of of madamaka thought.
I have only come across one physicist in
in my own physics background who took
eastern or let's say um that kind of
approach seriously and that was when I
did my PhD which was with David Bow in
college he used to have lots of
discussions with um Krishna Mertie and
and others too and seeking to find some
kind of um unity of thought between the
two or or at least one side informing
the other. Would you say that that um
the philosophy the Buddhist philosophy
that you've been thinking has something
specific to add to western thought that
we should take particular notice of?
Uh yeah. So I mean there has has been a
lot more interested in these uh uh
connection since the times of of David B
and and the tower physics and all of
these kind of um um earlier works. I
mean one um
example I've got that right here is in
Carlo Roi you know Helgoland I've got
that book. You've got that book and then
did a brief review of it on on YouTube.
Exactly. Okay. And then you'll realize
that um um in uh chapter five there is a
section called without foundations
Nagarajuna. Naggina is of course the the
founder of the school of Madyamaka that
we've just been talking about. And so
Ralli is is looking at the the extent to
which this kind of relationism
uh um uh which he is interested in in in
quantum physics can be related to
Negarina's idea that you don't have any
substances. Right? So there you have a
um an interesting dialogue there. That
is of course not that not to say that
you know they've they've already
discovered um quantum physics in second
century India. That would be absurd. The
idea is rather that we are looking for
theoretical models in order to explain
stuff that we want to explain now by
looking at intellectual traditions. And
this is this is this is what he's doing
there. Um another good example where
where these uh um connections are
explored is is a French physicist called
Michelle Bitbull. um he's published
mainly in French, not so much much in
English, but um he has al also um
presented quite a lot of interesting
material in in in looking at the
interconnection between these Madiama
ideas that um uh we've been talking
about and and and quantum physics. So
again, I think why this is interesting
is not some kind of philosophy science
vindication where you say okay well the
scientists say it too and therefore the
philosophy must be true. It's rather the
idea that you get specific philosophical
perspectives in these text that might
help you in order to generate a kind of
theoretical framework to explain what
you want to explain. Yeah. And that is I
think is interesting and if it's done in
a responsible way also quite
illuminating. Well, we're we're coming
to to the end of our time together.
Yeah. But I wanted to ask you if I may
one one last question which is more more
focused on your particular thoughts
having having studied
many of these different ideas. Now what
what is Yan Wester's view of conception
of reality as close as you can you can
define it.
Right. I I I put you on the spot a
little bit. No, no, no, no. I I think
the the of course the the short answer
it's it's a lot more complicated than we
have thought. Um I mean I don't I I
don't want to pretend that I've figured
it all out already and I that would be a
little bit boring perhaps because then
what else am I going to do with the rest
of my life? Um so um I mean what I what
I think has emerged from this from um
the discussion that we had so far is
that um there are a lot more theoretical
options out there about what kind of
structure reality could have. And some
of them are really underexplored and uh
deserve a lot more airtime in seeing how
they might be able to solve the
theoretical puzzles that we are
interested in. Yes. But but let me pin
you down further. What what of those
particular models would you choose if
you were forced to make a choice as to
this is what I think reality is really
at? It's either all mind or it's all
materialism or it's neither one or the
other or it's interactionism between the
two or it's I I don't know what would
you say is your closest understanding of
what reality really comes down to. Okay.
So there such a thing. Yeah. No. Okay.
This is I think the the um the there are
two two parts to the answer of this
question. So the first is of course that
you that if you assume that there are no
ultimately real objects then there's
also a good case to be made that there
are no ultimate truth either right and
so to that extent if you the the
question you know what what do you think
is really real or what what's the final
answer or what is the ultimate truth of
the onlogical structure of reality also
presupposes that there is such a thing
and that they specific facts about those
and if you deny that then the whole
question is uh is unfounded. Okay, so
that was the first part. Now the second
part is however if you think okay so
taking that into account and without
assuming that any of these um uh of
these models are reflective of the way
reality is fundamentally.
Um which one do you think is the best in
terms of comparison with all the others?
And uh there I would say well remember
we we talked about the the the tri of
foundationalism dependence all the way
down and the circular system is the the
what I'd be most interested in and I
think has has the the most theoretical
potential is the final one is is the the
circular structure where you have an
ontology of entities that are
interconnected in a web of dependence
and where they depend on one one another
where not necessarily everything depends
on everything else But everything
depends on some other thing. Yeah. So
that that is what my best bet would be.
That's a kind of bootstrap argument that
everything pulls itself up into reality.
That's right. Yan Weserov, thank you
very much indeed for your time today and
uh a probing into what reality may or
may not be, but thank you very much
indeed. Well, thank you very much,
Philip, to for inviting me. I really
enjoyed the conversation. [Music]
Click on any text or timestamp to jump to that moment in the video
Share:
Most transcripts ready in under 5 seconds
One-Click Copy125+ LanguagesSearch ContentJump to Timestamps
Paste YouTube URL
Enter any YouTube video link to get the full transcript
Transcript Extraction Form
Most transcripts ready in under 5 seconds
Get Our Chrome Extension
Get transcripts instantly without leaving YouTube. Install our Chrome extension for one-click access to any video's transcript directly on the watch page.
Works with YouTube, Coursera, Udemy and more educational platforms
Get Instant Transcripts: Just Edit the Domain in Your Address Bar!
YouTube
←
→
↻
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=UF8uR6Z6KLc
YoutubeToText
←
→
↻
https://youtubetotext.net/watch?v=UF8uR6Z6KLc